Difference between revisions of "Stated preferences do not align with revealed preferences"

From Harridanic
Jump to navigation Jump to search
(Created page with "Fancy way of saying that you cannot necessarily believe what people say they think in a survey. For example, in a survey on giving more money to charity, people are more like...")
 
Line 2: Line 2:
  
 
For example, in a survey on giving more money to charity, people are more likely to express the opinion that of course they'd give more to charity if X, Y or Z were to happen. However it is unlikely that everyone expressing that opinion would, in fact, give more money to charity when Y eventually does happen.
 
For example, in a survey on giving more money to charity, people are more likely to express the opinion that of course they'd give more to charity if X, Y or Z were to happen. However it is unlikely that everyone expressing that opinion would, in fact, give more money to charity when Y eventually does happen.
 +
 +
Another would be "how much do you drink" or "would you like to drink less" would receive answers the person being questioned thinks would paint them in a better light, rather than what a 'truer' answer would be.
  
 
To give a concrete example, [[Wakefield, Hayes, Durkin, and Borland (2013)]], has been used by [[tobacco control]] as justification that [[plain packaging]] was a success in Australia because people ''thought'' about quitting more when smoking cigarettes in [[plain packaging]]. Unfortunately no-one thought to follow up these thoughtful people to find out if they actually had given up.
 
To give a concrete example, [[Wakefield, Hayes, Durkin, and Borland (2013)]], has been used by [[tobacco control]] as justification that [[plain packaging]] was a success in Australia because people ''thought'' about quitting more when smoking cigarettes in [[plain packaging]]. Unfortunately no-one thought to follow up these thoughtful people to find out if they actually had given up.

Revision as of 12:57, 9 December 2016

Fancy way of saying that you cannot necessarily believe what people say they think in a survey.

For example, in a survey on giving more money to charity, people are more likely to express the opinion that of course they'd give more to charity if X, Y or Z were to happen. However it is unlikely that everyone expressing that opinion would, in fact, give more money to charity when Y eventually does happen.

Another would be "how much do you drink" or "would you like to drink less" would receive answers the person being questioned thinks would paint them in a better light, rather than what a 'truer' answer would be.

To give a concrete example, Wakefield, Hayes, Durkin, and Borland (2013), has been used by tobacco control as justification that plain packaging was a success in Australia because people thought about quitting more when smoking cigarettes in plain packaging. Unfortunately no-one thought to follow up these thoughtful people to find out if they actually had given up.